National Academies Press: OpenBook

In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition (2010)

Chapter: 15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby

« Previous: 14 A Role for Relaxed Selection in the Evolution of the Language Capacity--Terrence W. Deacon
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

15
Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence

LEDA COSMIDES,* H. CLARK BARRETT,* AND JOHN TOOBY*

Blank-slate theories of human intelligence propose that reasoning is carried out by general-purpose operations applied uniformly across contents. An evolutionary approach implies a radically different model of human intelligence. The task demands of different adaptive problems select for functionally specialized problem-solving strategies, unleashing massive increases in problem-solving power for ancestrally recurrent adaptive problems. Because exchange can evolve only if cooperators can detect cheaters, we hypothesized that the human mind would be equipped with a neurocognitive system specialized for reasoning about social exchange. Whereas humans perform poorly when asked to detect violations of most conditional rules, we predicted and found a dramatic spike in performance when the rule specifies an exchange and violations correspond to cheating. According to critics, people’s uncanny accuracy at detecting violations of social exchange rules does not reflect a cheater detection mechanism, but extends instead to all rules regulating when actions are permitted (deontic conditionals). Here we report experimental tests that falsify these theories by demonstrating that deontic rules as a class do not elicit the search for violations. We show that the cheater detection system functions with pinpoint accuracy, searching for violations of social exchange rules only when these are likely to reveal the presence of someone who intends to cheat. It does not search for violations of social exchange rules when these are accidental, when they do not benefit the violator, or when the situation would make cheating difficult.

*

Center for Evolutionary Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106; and

Department of Anthropology, University of California, Los Angeles, CA 90095.

To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: cosmides@psych.ucsb.edu.

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

To the human mind, certain things seem intuitively correct. The world seems flat and motionless; objects seem solid rather than composed of empty space, fields, and wave functions; space seems Euclidian and 3-dimensional rather than curved and 11-dimensional. Because scientists are equipped with human minds, they often take intuitive propositions for granted and import them—unexamined—into their scientific theories. Because they seem so self-evidently true, it can take centuries before these intuitive assumptions are questioned and, under the cumulative weight of evidence, discarded in favor of counterintuitive alternatives—a spinning Earth orbiting the sun, quantum mechanics, relativity.

For psychology and the cognitive sciences, the intuitive view of human intelligence and rationality—the blank-slate theory of the mind—may be just such a case of an intuition-fueled failure to grapple with evidence (Gallistel, 1990; Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2001; Pinker, 2002). According to intuition, intelligence—almost by definition—seems to be the ability to reason successfully about almost any topic. If we can reason about any content, from cabbages to kings, it seems self-evident that intelligence must operate by applying inference procedures that operate uniformly regardless of the content domains they are applied to (such procedures are general-purpose, domain-general, and content-independent). Consulting such intuitions, logicians and mathematicians developed content-independent formal systems over the last two centuries that operate in exactly this way. Such explicit formalization then allowed computer scientists to show how reasoning could be automatically carried out by purely “mechanical” operations (whether electronically in a computer or by cellular interactions in the brain). Accordingly, cognitive scientists began searching for cognitive programs implementing logic (Wason and Johnson-Laird, 1972; Rips, 1994), Bayes’ rule (Gigerenzer and Murray, 1987), multiple regression (Rumelhart et al., 1986), and other normative methods—the same content-general inferential tools that scientists themselves use for discovering what is true (Gigerenzer and Murray, 1987). Others proposed simpler heuristics that are more fallible than canonical rules of inference [e.g., Gigerenzer et al. (1999), Kahneman (2003)], but most of these were domain-general as well.

Our inferential toolbox does appear to contain a few domain-general devices (Rode et al., 1999; Gallistel and Gibbon, 2000; Cosmides and Tooby, 2001), but there are strong reasons to suspect that these must be supplemented with domain-specific elements as well. Why? To begin with, much—perhaps most—human reasoning diverges wildly from what would be observed if reasoning were based on canonical formal methods. Worse, if adherence to content-independent inferential methods constituted intelligence, then equipping computers with programs implement-

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

ing these methods, operating at vastly higher rates, should have made them intelligent. It did not. It turns out that general-purpose reasoning methods are very weak, and have crippling defects (e.g., combinatorial explosion) that are a direct consequence of their domain generality (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2001; Tooby et al., 2005). Also, content effects (changes in reasoning performance based on changes in content) are ubiquitous (Wason and Johnson-Laird, 1972; Gigerenzer and Murray, 1987) yet difficult to account for in the consensus view. After all, differences in content should make little difference to procedures whose operation is designed to be content-independent. Unfortunately, the effects of content on reasoning have traditionally been dismissed as noise to be ignored rather than a window on reasoning methods of a radically different, content-specific design.

INTELLIGENCE AND EVOLVED SPECIALIZATIONS

The integration of evolutionary biology with cognitive science led to a markedly different approach to investigating human intelligence and rationality: evolutionary psychology (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2001). Organisms are engineered systems that must operate effectively in real time to solve challenging adaptive problems. The computational problems our ancestors faced were not drawn randomly from the universe of all possible problems; instead, they were densely clustered in particular, recurrent families (e.g., predator avoidance, foraging, mating) that occupy only miniscule regions of the space of possible problems. Massive efficiency gains can be achieved when different computational strategies are tailored to the task demands of different problem types. For this reason, natural selection added a diverse array of inferential specializations, each tailored to a particular, adaptively important problem domain (Gallistel, 1990). Freed from the straightjacket of a one-size-fits-all problem-solving strategy, these reasoning specializations succeed by deploying procedures that produce adaptive inferences in a specific domain, even if these operations are invalid, useless, or harmful if activated outside that domain. They can do this by exploiting regularities—content-specific relationships—that hold true within the problem domain, but not outside of it. This approach naturally predicts content effects, because different content domains should activate different inferential rules.

In this view, human intelligence is more powerful than machine intelligence because it contains, alongside general-purpose inferential tools, a large and diverse array of adaptive specializations—expert systems, equipped with proprietary problem-solving strategies that evolved to match the recurrent features of their corresponding problem domains.

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

Indeed, the discovery of previously unknown adaptive specializations proceeded at a rapid pace once cognitive and evolutionary scientists became open to their existence and began to look for them (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992).

For nearly three decades, we have been studying human reasoning in the light of evolution (Cosmides, 1985, 1989; Cosmides and Tooby, 1989, 2005, 2008; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992; Fiddick et al., 2000, 2005; Stone et al., 2002; Sugiyama et al., 2002; Ermer et al., 2006; Reis et al., 2007). By integrating results from evolutionary game theory with the ecology of hunter-gatherer life, we developed social contract theory: a task analysis specifying what computational properties a neurocognitive system would need to generate adaptive inferences and behavior in the social exchange problem domain (Cosmides and Tooby, 1989). We have been systematically testing for the presence of these design features, including an important one: the ability to detect cheaters. Based on these investigations, we have proposed that the human mind reliably develops social contract algorithms: a set of programs built by natural selection for reasoning about social exchange (Cosmides, 1985, 1989; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2005, 2008). This system can reason adaptively about social exchange precisely because it does not perform the inferences of any standard formal logic.

EXCHANGE AS A COMPUTATIONAL PROBLEM

Selection Pressures for Social Exchange

Two parties can make themselves better off than they were before—thereby increasing their fitness—by exchanging things each values less for things each values more (goods, services, help). Exchange is found in every documented human culture, and takes many forms, such as returning favors, sharing food, and extending acts of help with the (implicit) expectation that they will be reciprocated. Behavioral ecology and hunter-gatherer ethnography have demonstrated that exchange is fundamental to forager subsistence and sociality (Gurven, 2004). Indeed, evidence suggests that certain forms of social exchange were present in hominins at least 2 million years ago (Isaac, 1978). This raises the possibility that selection has introduced computational elements that were well-engineered for social exchange.

Cognitive Defense Against Cheaters

Selection pressures favoring social exchange exist whenever one organism (the provisioner) can change the behavior of a target organism

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

to the provisioner’s advantage by making the target’s receipt of a rationed benefit conditional on the target acting in a required manner. This contingency can be expressed as a social contract, a conditional rule that fits the following template: If you accept benefit B from me, then you must satisfy my requirement R. The social contract is offered because the provisioner expects to be better off if its conditions are satisfied [e.g., if one gives the theater owner the price of a ticket (requirement R) in return for access to the symphony (benefit B)]. The target accepts these terms only if the benefit provided more than compensates for any losses he incurs by satisfying the requirement (e.g., if hearing the symphony is worth the cost of the ticket to him). This mutual provisioning of benefits, each conditional on the other’s compliance, is what is meant by social exchange or reciprocation (Cosmides, 1985; Cosmides and Tooby, 1989; Tooby and Cosmides, 1996). Understanding it requires a form of conditional reasoning that operates on abstract yet content-specific conceptual elements.

Algorithms generating social exchange require (i) a system for representing exchange situations in terms of conceptual primitives such as agent, rationed benefit, provisioner’s requirement, and entitlement; (ii) a system for mapping states of the world onto these proprietary concepts (e.g., the agent is the theater owner; the rationed benefit is access to the symphony; the requirement is payment of the ticket price); and (iii) domain-specialized rules of inference that operate on these conceptual primitives, supplying inferences that are necessary to carry out the system’s evolved function [rules of logic do not supply the necessary inferences (Cosmides, 1989; Fiddick et al., 2000; Cosmides and Tooby, 2008)].

Adaptations for delivering benefits to unrelated individuals will be selected against unless the losses one incurs by delivering benefits are compensated for by the reciprocal delivery of benefits. Consequently, the existence of cheaters—those who fail to deliver compensatory benefits—threatens the evolution of exchange. Using evolutionary game theory, it has been shown that adaptations for social exchange can be favored and stably maintained by natural selection, but only if they include design features that enable them to detect cheaters, and cause them to channel future exchanges to reciprocators and away from cheaters (Trivers, 1971; Axelrod, 1984; Tooby and Cosmides, 1996).

Cheater Detection Is Person Categorization and Not Event Categorization

Indeed, the exact nature of the adaptive problem posed by cheaters determines how social contract algorithms should have evolved to define the concept cheater. A cheater is an agent who (i) takes the rationed benefit offered in a social exchange but (ii) fails to meet the provisioner’s

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

requirement, and (iii) does so by intention rather than by mistake or accident. The evolutionary function of a cheater detection subroutine is to defend the cooperator against exploitation. It is designed to represent and track the other party’s behavior so that it can (when warranted) correctly connect an attributed disposition (to cheat) with that particular person (who thereby becomes categorized as a cheater). In the experiments reported here, we manipulate these cheater-defining elements and demonstrate that they regulate reasoning about conditional rules involving social exchange.

The conceptual primitive cheater along with domain-specific inference rules for detecting cheaters were predicted to be a central part of social exchange reasoning because they are necessary to solve a computational problem that, if unsolved, would prevent the evolution of social exchange. Together, they constitute a logic of social exchange—a content-specialized logic whose conceptual primitives, inference rules, and outputs are quite different from those produced by standard formal logics, such as the predicate calculus. The need for special inferential rules for cheater detection derives from the fact that standard, domain-general conditional reasoning rules will fail to identify cheaters in many circumstances, and will misidentify reciprocators and altruists as cheaters in others (Cosmides, 1989; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2005, 2008).

Evolutionary Versus Economic and Other Functions

A cheater is someone who has violated a social contract—a conditional rule involving social exchange—but not all violations of social contracts reveal the presence of a cheater. This fact allows critical tests between an evolutionary and an economic perspective. A commonplace of economics, utility theory, and common sense is that people become adept at solving problems that they are motivated to solve, such as those that have economic consequences. When targets violate a social contract, the provisioner suffers a loss in utility; if these cases are detected, the provisioner could insist on getting what she is owed. If such economic consequences drive the acquisition of reasoning skills, then people should be good at detecting all violations of social contracts because this will allow them to recoup their losses. It would not matter whether the violation occurred by mistake or on purpose, or whether it benefited the violator—the provisioner has suffered a loss in all of these cases. These distinctions do matter, however, if evolution produced a subroutine specialized for detecting cheaters.

The function of a cheater detection subroutine is social categorization: this person=cheater. The fitness benefit that drove the evolution of cheater detection is the ability to avoid squandering costly future coopera-

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

tive efforts on those who will exploit rather than reciprocate. Violations of social contracts are relevant to this evolved function, but only insofar as they reveal individuals disposed to cheat—that is, individuals who cheat by virtue of their calibration or design. Noncompliance caused by accidental violations and other innocent mistakes do not reveal the disposition to cheat. Hence, they should not be encoded by social contract algorithms as cheating—even though the payoff to the provisioner is the same as cheating. That is, accidental violations may result in someone being cheated (not getting what they are entitled to), but they do not indicate the ongoing menace of a cheater.

Therefore, social contract theory predicts cognitive design features beyond detecting compliance or noncompliance with a social contract. The subroutine should be designed to look for potentially intentional violations, because only these predict future defection and continued exploitation—the negative outcome the system evolved to defend itself against. Indeed, results from evolutionary game theory show that strategies for conditional cooperation do better if they can “see through” failures to reciprocate due to chance, because they continue to reap the benefits of cooperating with other conditional cooperators who may have erred [e.g., Panchanathan and Boyd (2003)]. The surprising social contract prediction—that noncompliance in social exchanges is only detected at high rates when it could reveal cheaters—is tested in the experiments reported below.

Cue-Based Activation of Cheater Detection

To achieve their large efficiency gains, adaptive specializations should be designed to be differentially activated when they encounter the content domains they are equipped to solve, and inactive when they encounter other content domains where their proprietary operations are inapplicable, mismatched, or invalid (Tooby and Cosmides, 1992; Tooby et al., 2005). This point is central to understanding the logic of the experiments reported here: If there is an evolved inference system specialized for reasoning about social exchange, then the cheater detection subroutine should be differentially activated by content cues signaling the potential for determining whether someone is a cheater. The strategy pursued in these experiments is to add and subtract minimal problem elements that are irrelevant to competing theories of reasoning but that should activate or inactivate the cheater detection subroutine because they allow or interfere with the determination of whether someone is a cheater. The elements we will concentrate on are: (i) Is there a benefit being rationed? (if not, there is no social exchange); (ii) Could the other party benefit by violation of the rule? (if not, then detecting a violation will not identify

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

a cheater); (iii) Did the violator have the intention to cheat? (if not, then detecting a violation will not identify a cheater); and (iv) Does the situation make cheating difficult? (if so, then looking for violations is unlikely to reveal cheaters).

EXPERIMENTAL TESTS OF SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY

Exchange is, by definition, social behavior that is conditional: The provisioner agrees to deliver a benefit conditionally (conditional on the recipient doing what the provisioner required). Engaging in social exchange therefore requires conditional reasoning.

Our experiments use the Wason selection task, a standard tool for investigating conditional reasoning (Wason and Johnson-Laird, 1972). Subjects are given a conditional rule of the form if P then Q, and asked to identify possible violations of it—a format that allows one to see how performance varies as a function of the rule’s content (Fig. 15.1A). It was originally developed to determine whether humans are natural falsificationists—whether the brain spontaneously applies first-order logic to look for cases that might violate a hypothesis or other conditional rule. To their surprise, psychologists found that people perform poorly when asked to solve this simple problem.

According to first-order logic, a conditional rule has the form if antecedent (conventionally represented by P) then consequent (conventionally represented by Q). Looking for violations of a conditional rule is a remarkably simple task: According to first-order logic, the rule is violated whenever P is true but Q is not—that is, by the co-occurrence of P & not-Q. For example, the rule “if a person is a biologist, then that person enjoys camping” would be violated by finding a biologist who does not enjoy camping. In a Wason selection task involving this rule, there would be four cards, each representing a different individual. One side would tell whether that individual is a biologist, and the other side would tell whether he or she enjoys camping (see Fig. 15.1). To find out whether the preferences of any of these individuals violate the rule, one would need to investigate the biologist (P card) to see if he does not enjoy camping, and the person who does not enjoy camping (not-Q card) to see if this person is a biologist. Thus, a fully correct Wason response would be to choose P, not-Q, and no other cards.

First-order logic is simple to specify—vastly simpler than many other cognitive capacities that humans are known to have, such as vision and grammar acquisition. It is also prototypically content-independent and domain-general: It maps all of the content of conditional rules into the format if antecedent then consequent, where the antecedent and consequent can stand for any propositions. It can be informative about nearly

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
FIGURE 15.1 (A) The general structure of a Wason selection task. The rule always has specific content; e.g., “if a person is a biologist, then that person enjoys camping” (an indicative rule). For this rule, each card would represent a different person, reading, for example, “biologist” (P), “chemist” (not-P), “enjoys camping” (Q), “does not enjoy camping” (not-Q). The content of the rule can be varied such that the rule is indicative, a social contract, a precaution, a permission rule, or any other conditional of interest, allowing alternative theories of reasoning to be tested. Checkmarks indicate the logically correct card choices. (B) General structure of a Wason task when the conditional rule is a social contract. A social contract can be translated into either social contract terms (benefits and requirements) or logical terms (Ps and Qs). Checkmarks indicate the correct card choices if one is looking for cheaters—these should be chosen by a cheater detection subroutine, whether the exchange was expressed in a standard format (i.e., benefit to potential violator in antecedent clause) or a switched format (benefit in consequent clause). This results in a logically incorrect answer (Q & not-P) when the rule is expressed in the switched format, and a logically correct answer (P & not-Q) when the rule is expressed in the standard format. Tests of switched social contracts have shown that the reasoning procedures activated cause one to detect cheaters, not logical violations. Note that a logically correct response to a switched social contract—where P = requirement satisfied and not-Q = benefit not accepted—would fail to detect cheaters.

FIGURE 15.1 (A) The general structure of a Wason selection task. The rule always has specific content; e.g., “if a person is a biologist, then that person enjoys camping” (an indicative rule). For this rule, each card would represent a different person, reading, for example, “biologist” (P), “chemist” (not-P), “enjoys camping” (Q), “does not enjoy camping” (not-Q). The content of the rule can be varied such that the rule is indicative, a social contract, a precaution, a permission rule, or any other conditional of interest, allowing alternative theories of reasoning to be tested. Checkmarks indicate the logically correct card choices. (B) General structure of a Wason task when the conditional rule is a social contract. A social contract can be translated into either social contract terms (benefits and requirements) or logical terms (Ps and Qs). Checkmarks indicate the correct card choices if one is looking for cheaters—these should be chosen by a cheater detection subroutine, whether the exchange was expressed in a standard format (i.e., benefit to potential violator in antecedent clause) or a switched format (benefit in consequent clause). This results in a logically incorrect answer (Q & not-P) when the rule is expressed in the switched format, and a logically correct answer (P & not-Q) when the rule is expressed in the standard format. Tests of switched social contracts have shown that the reasoning procedures activated cause one to detect cheaters, not logical violations. Note that a logically correct response to a switched social contract—where P = requirement satisfied and not-Q = benefit not accepted—would fail to detect cheaters.

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

everything. Finally, the inferential rules of first-order logic are incapable of responding differentially to particular contents, because they do not represent content at all. All its rules see are its conceptual primitives (e.g., antecedent, consequent, if, then).

The biologist-camping rule is indicative: It claims to indicate or describe some relationship in the world. Given an indicative conditional, only 5–30% of normal subjects respond with the logically correct answer, P & not-Q. Most do choose P, but about half omit not-Q, many choose Q, and a few choose not-P. Although one might think that people would learn to reason correctly about familiar relationships, performance remains poor even when the indicative rule involves very familiar content drawn from direct experience—such as, if I eat cereal, then I drink orange juice (Wason, 1983; Cosmides, 1985). Either our species did not evolve a full and unimpaired version of first-order logic, or significant parts of it are not activated when people try to solve this simple information search task.

Although originally designed to test whether people had a content-general system for conditional reasoning, the Wason task can be and has been used to test many of the predictions of social contract theory [for reviews, see Cosmides and Tooby (2005, 2008)]. The hypothesis that the brain contains social contract algorithms predicts that reasoning performance should shift when it encounters social exchange content. In particular, it predicts a sharply enhanced ability to reason adaptively about conditional rules when those rules specify a social exchange.

Content is indeed decisive. Although performance on the Wason selection task is typically poor, when the conditional rule involves social exchange and detecting a violation corresponds to looking for cheaters, 65–80% of subjects correctly detect violations (Cosmides, 1985, 1989; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992; Cosmides and Tooby, 2005, 2008). Confounding the idea that people improve only with increasing experience, subjects perform well even when the conditional rule specifies a wildly unfamiliar social contract that no subject has ever heard before (e.g., “if you get a tattoo on your face, then I’ll give you cassava root”). Indeed, we have found no difference in performance between totally unfamiliar social contracts and thoroughly familiar ones. Moreover, the ability to detect cheaters on social contracts is present as early as it can be tested (ages 3–4) (Harris et al., 2001). Consistent with the hypothesis that this adaptive specialization is part of our species’ cognitive architecture, this pattern of results has been found in every culture where it has been tested, from industrialized market economies to Shiwiar hunter horticulturalists of the Ecuadorian Amazon (Sugiyama et al., 2002).

Because the correct answer if one is looking for cheaters is sometimes the logically correct answer as well, many people misunderstand us to be claiming that social exchange content boosts logical reasoning. But social

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

exchange activates nonstandard rules of inference that diverge sharply from first-order logic. The adaptively correct answer when one is looking for cheaters is to choose cards representing people who have taken the benefit and not met the requirement, regardless of the logical category into which these fall. It is possible to create social exchange problems in which these correspond to a logically incorrect answer: Q & not-P (see Fig. 15.1B). When this was done, subjects’ selections matched the predictions of the nonstandard evolutionary logic of social exchange and violated first-order logic. Q and not-P choices were predicted from first principles, and had never been predicted by any other theory, or previously elicited (Cosmides, 1985, 1989; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992).

Deontic Logic or Social Contract Algorithms?

Most reasoning researchers now concede that (i) content effects for social exchanges are real, replicable, and robust; and (ii) first-order logic cannot explain how people reason about social exchange. However, they continue to resist the counterintuitive notion that reasoning in this domain is governed by an adaptive specialization. Instead, they propose that reasoning about social exchange is governed by some version of deontic logic—a formal system for reasoning about concepts such as permission and obligation. Social contracts do involve deontic concepts, so this is a plausible proposal. However, the universe of deontic rules is far larger than social contracts, extending to moral rules, imperatives, norms, and so on. If the mind comes equipped with (or acquires) some form of deontic logic, then people should be good at detecting violations of all deontic rules (Cheng and Holyoak, 1985; Fodor, 2000), or at least those involving utilities (Manktelow and Over, 1990, 1991; Sperber et al., 1995).

In support of the deontic position, its advocates point out that another type of deontic conditional that we and others have worked on also elicits good violation detection on the Wason task: precautionary rules (Cheng and Holyoak, 1989; Manktelow and Over, 1990; Fiddick et al., 2000; Stone et al., 2002; Ermer et al., 2006). These are conditionals that fit the template “if one is to engage in hazardous activity H, then one must take precaution R” (e.g., “if you are working with toxic gases, then you must wear a gas mask”). Precautionary rules are so similar to social contracts that most theories view them as trivial variations on a theme—deontic conditionals involving utilities, processed by precisely the same reasoning system (Cheng and Holyoak, 1989; Manktelow and Over, 1990, 1991; Kirby, 1994; Oaksford and Chater, 1994; Sperber et al., 1995).

By contrast, evolutionary researchers have proposed that these rules are processed not by social contract algorithms but by a different specialization with a distinct function: to monitor for cases in which people are in

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

danger by virtue of not having taken the appropriate precaution (Fiddick et al., 2000; Boyer and Lienard, 2006). Neuroimaging results and evidence that brain damage can selectively impair social exchange reasoning (while sparing precautionary reasoning) support the evolutionary hypothesis that these are two distinct specializations, not one superordinate deontic system (Stone et al., 2002; Fiddick et al., 2005; Ermer et al., 2006; Reis et al., 2007). Moreover, an adaptationist perspective predicts that subjects should detect accidental as well as intentional violations of precautionary rules, because both place people in danger—a prediction now tested and confirmed (Fiddick, 2004). By contrast, intentionality should matter in exchanges because unintentional violations do not reveal cheaters—a prediction we test below.

New Tests Between Deontic and Social Exchange Theories

In exchange, an agent permits another party to take a benefit, conditional upon that party’s having met the agent’s requirement. There are, however, many situations other than exchange in which an action is permitted conditionally. A permission rule is any deontic conditional that fits the template “if one is to take action A, then one must satisfy precondition R” (Cheng and Holyoak, 1985, 1989). According to Cheng and Holyoak’s (1985) permission schema theory, reasoning about such rules is governed by four production rules that result in people checking the “action taken” card (P) and the “precondition not met” card (not-Q). We focus on their account because it is the most precisely specified of the deontic accounts. But our experiments also test against all other deontic theories known to us.

It is important to remember that all social contracts are permission rules, but there are many permission rules that are not social contracts. According to permission schema theory, good violation detection is elicited by the entire class of permission rules (Cheng and Holyoak, 1985, 1989)—a far more inclusive and general set that includes precautionary rules, bureaucratic rules, etiquette rules, and social norms, along with social contracts.

Empirically, permission schema theory is undermined or falsified if permission rules that are neither social contracts nor precautions routinely fail to elicit high levels of violation detection. Moreover, social contract theory is supported if social exchange rules (a subset of permission rules) fail to elicit this effect when violation detection does not identify cheaters.

Just how precise and functionally specialized is the reasoning system that causes cheater detection? Below we report the results of four experiments that parametrically test predictions about benefits, intentionality, and the ability to cheat on social contracts. The full text of all Wason tasks tested is available online at www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/0914623107/DCSupplemental

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

(hereinafter referred to as SI Text). All experiments had a between-subjects design in which each subject was given a single Wason task. In every case, the rule tested was a permission rule: a deontic conditional that fits the template “if one is to take action A, then one must satisfy precondition R.” For the problems tested, the correct answer if one is looking for violations of the rule is to choose the P card (action taken), the not-Q card (requirement not met), and no others (henceforth P & not-Q).

PERMISSION RULES WITHOUT BENEFITS

The function of a social exchange for each participant is to gain access to a benefit that would otherwise be unavailable to them. Therefore, an important cue that a conditional rule is a social contract is the presence of a desired benefit under the control of an agent—this should activate social contract reasoning. Experiments 1 and 2 compare performance on permission rules that vary a single element: whether P, the action to be taken, is a benefit to the potential violator. They show that this has a dramatic effect on performance.

Experiment 1

Wason tasks consist of a rule and a story setting the context (what the cards refer to, who proposed the rule, and so on). In experiment 1, we kept the stories identical, and made small but theoretically relevant alterations to the rule. By changing P to an action that our subjects would spontaneously recognize as a benefit, a permission rule was transformed into a social contract. A two-word change was sufficient (see below, rules 1 and 2).

Experiment 1 compared performance on three permission rules, each described as a law made by a group of tribal elders (SI Text). The story context, which was minimal, was identical for rules 1 and 2, and nearly so for rule 3. The four cards represented what four different members of the tribe had done, and subjects were asked which card(s) they would need to turn over to see whether any of these people had broken the law.

The tribal context allowed the use of permission rules that would be unfamiliar to the subjects (no italics in the originals):

  1. “If one is going out at night, then one must tie a small piece of red volcanic rock around one’s ankle.”

  2. “If one is staying home at night, then one must tie a small piece of red volcanic rock around one’s ankle.”

  3. “If one is taking out the garbage, then one must tie a small piece of red volcanic rock around one’s ankle.”

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

The italic portion of these permission rules specifies an action that one is permitted to take only if a requirement is met (the red rock is worn). What varies is whether this action is a benefit to the potential violator. Our subjects were undergraduates, for whom going out at night (rule 1) is a highly favored activity. Staying home at night (rule 2) is usually neutral: it is what you do when you have too much work, do not have a date, etc. Taking out garbage (rule 3) is a mildly unpleasant chore.

From the standpoint of permission schema theory, there is no theoretical difference between rules 1–3. Permission rules regulate when an action can be taken—whether that action benefits the potential violator or not. Cheng and Holyoak (1989) are very clear on this point; indeed, it is the basis for their claim that high performance on precautionary rules (where the action taken is hazardous and unpleasant) supports the existence of a permission schema. If permission schema theory is correct, all three rules will elicit high levels of violation detection, resulting in equally high percentages of P & not-Q responses.

Benefits play no role in permission schema theory, but they play a key role in social contract theory. Because rule 1 regulates access to an activity that our subjects recognize as a benefit, it should be interpreted as a social contract. This should activate the cheater detection mechanism, leading to a high level of P & not-Q responses. In contrast, rules 2 and 3 do not regulate access to a benefit. Lacking this key element, they are less likely to be interpreted as social contracts, and less likely to activate cheater detection. For this reason, social contract theory predicts that rules 2 and 3 will yield a significantly lower percentage of P & not-Q responses than rule 1.

That is precisely what happened. Rule 1—the social contract—elicited the correct response (P & not-Q) from 80% of subjects (20/25). Only 52% of subjects (13/25) answered correctly for rule 2, and 44% (11/25) for rule 3. Both of these percentages are significantly lower than that found for the social contract (80% vs. 52%: Z = 2.09, P = 0.018, Φ = 0.30; 80% vs. 44%: Z = 2.62, P = 0.0044, Φ = 0.37). Rules 1 and 2 are true minimal pairs: They differ by only two words (going out vs. staying home)—a trivial difference of no importance for permission schema theory. Yet this two-word difference, which affects whether the antecedent is a benefit or not, caused a drop in performance of 26 percentage points. The garbage problem was included because the less pleasant the activity being regulated, the lower the probability that subjects will interpret the rule as a social contract; this predicts a monotonic decrease in performance from going out to staying home to garbage. Contrast analysis confirms this (several monotonically decreasing models work, with λ = +3, –1, –2 providing the best fit, Z = 3.06, P = 0.0011; see also note 1 of SI Text).

Note that rule 3, the garbage rule, is capable of eliciting high levels of violation detection. In a parallel study, 72% of subjects (18/25) answered

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

correctly when the garbage rule was embedded in a story indicating that the people of this tribe view it as precautionary—that is, when taking out the garbage involves hazards that can be avoided by wearing the rock [72% (precautionary) vs. 44% (not precautionary): Z = 2.01, P = 0.02, Φ = 0.28; see experiment 5 of supporting information (SI Text)]. This illustrates an important point: High levels of violation detection are typically found for social contracts and for precautionary rules, but not for permission rules that fall outside these categories. The garbage and staying home problems in experiment 1 elicited poorer performance because they were not social contracts or precautionary.

What about the requirement term? A rule is a social contract if it regulates access to a benefit; it does not matter whether the requirement the individual must satisfy to be entitled to that benefit is personally costly, neutral, or even beneficial. The requirement is imposed not because it is costly to the person who must satisfy it, but because doing so creates a situation that the agent who imposed it wants to achieve. In a separate study, we confirmed this prediction: Varying whether the requirement is costly or beneficial to the potential violator had no effect on performance (experiment 1-A, SI Text).

Experiment 2

Experiment 2 is a conceptual replication of experiment 1, using the 1970s-era Sears problem:

  1. “You work as an assistant at Sears. You have the job of checking sales receipts to make sure that any sale over $30 has been approved by the section manager (this is a rule of the store).”

The cards, which have information about four sales receipts, read “$70,” “$15,” “signed,” and “not signed” (SI Text). D’Andrade [in Rumelhart and Norman (1981)] reports performance of ~70% on this problem.

According to Cosmides (1985, 1989), performance on the Sears problem is high because it engages the social contract algorithms. Sears is an institution devoted to social exchange, with policies to prevent cheating—checking credit cards and driver’s licenses, asking for phone numbers on checks, and so on. The more expensive the item, the worse it is for the store when people do not pay. Requiring manager approval for expensive items is one way stores protect themselves from potential cheaters: The manager approves the expensive purchase only when there are indications that the customer will be able to pay. The rule therefore regulates access to a benefit: goods worth more than $30 versus those worth less. Others dispute this interpretation, arguing that the Sears problem is a permission rule but not a social contract, and that high performance on this problem

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

demonstrates the existence of a reasoning mechanism general to the class of deontic rules (Cheng and Holyoak, 1989; Manktelow and Over, 1990).

There is no need to engage in verbal arguments when these two views can be tested empirically by comparing performance on rule 4, the original Sears problem, with closely matching rules that do not regulate access to a benefit. To this end, we created permission rules that are about inventory forms rather than sales receipts, such as:

  1. “You work as an assistant at Sears. Each department at Sears (Menswear, Sportswear, Ladies Shoes, etc.) has a different color inventory form to fill out. You have the job of checking inventory forms that the department clerks have filled out to make sure that any blue inventory form has been signed by the section manager. (This is a rule of the store.)” (Cards read: “blue,” “white,” “signed,” “not signed.”)

By making the rule about inventory forms, we have created a permission rule that subjects are unlikely to interpret as a rule regulating access to a benefit: It is unclear how anyone might benefit by filling out a blue inventory form rather than a white one. If high performance on rule 4 was caused by social contract algorithms, then performance on rule 5 should be lower. By contrast, a permission schema should generate equally high performance on rules 4 and 5.

Contrary to the predictions of permission schema theory, performance on the Sears inventory problem was significantly lower than performance on the original Sears problem: 72% correct (18/25) on rule 4 versus 48% correct (12/25) on rule 5 (Z = 1.73, P = 0.04, Φ = 0.24). Can it be pushed even lower by removing elements relevant to social exchange?

Most people know that requiring signatures is a common device to protect against cheating; the fact that a manager’s signature is required for blue inventory forms could suggest to some that valuable goods are being tracked by the blue forms, but not the white ones. To remove any hint that P might represent access to something more valuable than not-P, we created rule 6, an inventory rule that regulates where blue forms are to be filed (SI Text). The first two sentences were the same as for rule 5, but it continued as follows:

  1. “Filled out inventory forms are to be filed in various bins. You have the job of checking inventory forms that the department clerks have filled out to make sure that any blue inventory form has been filed in the metal bin. (This is a rule of the store.)” (Cards read: “blue,” “white,” “metal bin,” “wood bin.”)

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

Performance was even lower in response to rule 6: 32% correct (8/25). Yet it is a permission rule set in a culturally familiar context. Consistent with the view that performance should decrease with the removal of cues suggesting a benefit is being regulated, contrast analysis confirms a monotonic decrease from sales receipts (72%) to signed inventory forms (48%) to filed inventory forms (32%) (with P ≤ 0.0012, Z ≥ 3.04 for λ = 3, −1, −2 and 1, 0, −1).

These results support social contract theory and disconfirm permission schema theory. Indeed, they refute any theory [including Fodor’s (2000)] that attributes good violation detection to the entire domain of deontic rules.

Cheater detection has a signature: Benefit accepted and requirement not met are chosen, regardless of logical category. That the conditional rule regulates access to a benefit is a necessary condition for eliciting the detection of this very precise type of violation (Cosmides, 1989; Fiddick et al., 2000). It is not, however, a sufficient condition (Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992)—a prediction that we test in experiments 3 and 4.

INTENTIONAL VIOLATIONS VERSUS INNOCENT MISTAKES

Intentionality plays no role in permission schema theory. Whenever the action has been taken but the precondition has not been satisfied, the permission schema should register that a violation has occurred. As a result, people should be good at detecting violations of permission rules, whether the violations occurred by accident or by intention. Other deontic theories make the same prediction, because their explanations rest on how the rule is interpreted, not on properties of the violator.

By contrast, the evolved function of a cheater detection subroutine is to use cues of an intentional failure to meet the requirement to correctly connect an attributed disposition (to cheat) with a person (a cheater), for the reasons outlined above. Accidental violations may result in someone not getting what they are entitled to, but without indicating the presence of a cheater. Social contract theory therefore predicts that the same social contract rule will elicit lower violation detection when the context suggests that violations were occurring by mistake rather than by intention (Cosmides and Tooby, 1989; Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992). One partial test showed lowered violation detection when the individuals who might mistakenly violate the social contract were not in a position to obtain the benefit regulated by it (Fiddick, 2004). However, as the benefits experiments above make clear, this lower performance might have been due to the lack of a benefit to the violator, and not to intentionality at all.

We designed experiments 3 and 4 to clearly test whether intentionality regulates violation detection in social exchanges and, if so, to pinpoint

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

exactly what cues activate or inactivate social contract algorithms. If the cheater detection mechanism is designed to check whether the potential violator has obtained the benefit specified in the rule, then we would see a drop in performance when the violator will not obtain that benefit—even if his violation was intentional. Another possibility is that the cheater detection mechanism is not activated by innocent mistakes—even when the rule violator gets the benefit regulated by the rule by making this mistake. A third possibility is that the social exchange system is designed to respond to both of these factors.

Experiment 3:
Intentionality Without Benefits

In this study, the social contract rule was held constant; what varied was whether the potential violators were (i) cheaters (individuals who intend to violate the rule to obtain the regulated benefit); (ii) saboteurs (individuals who intend to violate the rule, but do so to obtain another benefit, rather than the benefit regulated by the rule); or (iii) people who may have made innocent mistakes (no intention to violate, no benefit gained by doing so).

The social contract regulated access to a very high quality school, Dover High. The story explains that it is a great school with an excellent record for placing students in good colleges; the neighboring school, Hanover High, is mediocre, with poor teachers and decrepit facilities. The story further explains that Dover High is good because the people of Dover City pay high taxes to support it; in contrast, the equally prosperous people of Hanover and Belmont (neighboring communities) have not been willing to spend the money it would take to improve Hanover High.

Taking these factors into account, the Board of Education made rule 7:

  1. “If a student is to be assigned to Dover High School, then that student must live in Dover City.”

In all versions, subjects are asked to imagine that they supervise four volunteers at the Board of Education who are supposed to follow rule 7. Each card represents the documents of one student, and the subject is asked which they need to turn over to see whether the documents of any of these students violate the rule.

In the cheater condition, each volunteer is the mother of a teenager who is about to enter high school, and each processed her own child’s documents; the concern is that some might have cheated. In the innocent mistake condition, the volunteers are helpful elderly ladies who have become absent-minded; the concern is that some might have violated

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

the rule by mistake. In the sabotage condition, the volunteers are mad at you for having fired their best friend; the concern is that they intend to violate the rule, with the goal of creating chaos that will make you look incompetent in the eyes of your boss.

Performance was best in the cheater condition and worst in the innocent mistake condition: 68% versus 27% correct (23/34 vs. 9/33; P = 0.0005, Φ = 0.40). The sabotage condition elicited intermediate performance of 45% correct (15/33)—significantly worse than the cheater condition (P = 0.033, Φ = 0.22) and marginally better than the innocent mistake condition (P = 0.06, Φ = 0.19). Contrast analysis confirms a linear decrease in performance in the cheater, sabotage, and innocent mistake conditions (λ = +1, 0, −1:Z = 3.62, P = 0.00015), and performance on all three was significantly better than on two other permission rules tested that were not social contracts at all, one using rule 7 (10−6 < Ps < 0.047; SI Text).

The results indicate that the cheater detection mechanism is most strongly activated by situations suggesting there are individuals who (i) intend to violate a social contract rule, and (ii) will gain the benefit it regulates by doing so. Removing the ability to gain this benefit while retaining the intention to violate decreased performance by ~20 percentage points; removing both factors decreased performance by ~40 percentage points.

Experiment 4 tests this interpretation in a full parametric study. It tests whether the effects of these variables are independent, and whether accidental violations decrease performance even when the violator will benefit from her mistake.

Experiment 4:
Manipulating Intentions, Benefits, and Ability

Eight Wason problems were tested, all using the same social contract—a version of rule 7 (“If a student is to be assigned to Grover High School, then that student must live in Grover City”). The story provided the same explanation as before: Grover High is better than Hanover High, and access to this benefit is restricted to students living in the community that pays higher taxes to support it (SI Text).

Everything about the problems was held as constant as possible, while three variables were manipulated: (i) whether the volunteers intended to violate the rule (intention present vs. absent); (ii) whether the volunteers could gain the benefit regulated by the rule by violating it (benefit present vs. absent); and (iii) whether the ability to easily cheat was present or absent. These three variables were fully crossed in a 2 × 2 × 2, between-subjects design.

The search for rule violations is unlikely to reveal individuals with a disposition to cheat when the situation prevents cheating. The ability vari-

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

able was included to see whether cheater detection is relaxed under these circumstances. In real life, some situations preclude cheating (Gigerenzer and Hug, 1992), either by both parties (e.g., simultaneous exchange of goods; working jointly on a shared project) or by one party (e.g., having done a favor in advance of reciprocation precludes cheating by the favor doer). In other situations, measures are taken to make cheating more difficult. To simulate the latter situation, the ability-absent conditions said that students were identified by code numbers so that the volunteers could not know which documents belonged to which child. This information was omitted from the ability-present conditions.

As above, benefit-present conditions explained that each volunteer is the mother of a teenager who is about to enter high school, and each processed her own child’s documents. Benefit-absent conditions said none of the four volunteers have children in school and so could not benefit from misassigning students. Intention present conditions said you (the supervisor) overheard that some of your volunteers intended to try to break the rules when it came to assigning children to schools (or “mischievously intended,” to create a motive for this intention in the benefit-absent conditions). Intention-absent conditions explained that you believe your volunteers are honest, but suspect they may have made some innocent mistakes and broken the rules for assigning each child to a particular school. The percentage of subjects correctly detecting violations by choosing the Grover High card (P), the town of Hanover card (not-Q), and no others is shown for each condition in Fig. 15.2.

The results were remarkably clear: Each factor—benefit, intention, and ability—contributed to violation detection, independently and additively (three-way ANOVA, main effects: Benefit F1,342 = 7.30, P = 0.007, η = 0.14; Intention F1,342 = 10.22, P = 0.002, η = 0.17; Ability F1,342 = 4.87, P = 0.028, η = 0.12; no interactions). The percentage of subjects who answered correctly was 64% when all three factors were present (BIA), 46% when only two factors were present (BI, BA, or IA), and 26% when only one factor was present (B, I, or A)—the same performance found when no factors were present. That is, each time a factor was removed, performance dropped by about 20 percentage points. This is the same pattern found in experiment 3, where ability to cheat was always present: 68% correct for the three-factor cheater condition (BIA), 45% correct for the two-factor sabotage condition (IA), and 27% correct for the one-factor innocent mistake condition (A) (SI Text, note 2).

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
FIGURE 15.2 Parametric study of social contract reasoning. In all conditions, subjects were asked to look for violations of the same social contract. What varied was whether potential violators could benefit by violating the rule (B), whether their violating the rule was by intention or by mistake (I), and whether the situation provided them with the ability to easily violate it (A). When all three factors were present (BIA), performance was highest. It dropped significantly when only two factors were present (BI, BA, IA), and again when only one factor was present (B, I, A)—to the same low level found when none of these factors were present.

FIGURE 15.2 Parametric study of social contract reasoning. In all conditions, subjects were asked to look for violations of the same social contract. What varied was whether potential violators could benefit by violating the rule (B), whether their violating the rule was by intention or by mistake (I), and whether the situation provided them with the ability to easily violate it (A). When all three factors were present (BIA), performance was highest. It dropped significantly when only two factors were present (BI, BA, IA), and again when only one factor was present (B, I, A)—to the same low level found when none of these factors were present.

DISCUSSION

Problems with Deontic and Other Theories

Experiments 1–4 falsify every deontic theory that we are aware of: ones that apply to the entire class of deontic rules, as well as ones that apply only to those involving utilities. Why? If high performance on social contracts were due to the ability to do well on deontic rules, then subjects should routinely do well on problems where the deontic rules are neither

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

social contracts nor precautions. They do not. In all cases tested in these experiments, subjects did poorly on deontic rules that did not allow the detection of a cheater. This was true even for social contracts, which are deontic permission rules involving utilities: Performance was high when detecting violations would reveal cheaters, but low when it would not.

Interpretation Theories Ruled Out

Most theories attempting to explain the spike in violation detection for deontic rules focus on how the rule itself is interpreted. These theories claim that violations are detected because deontic conditionals are interpreted as implying either (i) the inferences of a permission schema (Cheng and Holyoak, 1985); (ii) the slightly more general (but otherwise identical) inferences of the material conditional in first-order logic (Almor and Sloman, 1996); (iii) that cases of P & not-Q are forbidden [relevance theory (Sperber et al., 1995)]; or (iv) that Q is required (Fodor, 2000). None of these theories can explain the results of experiments 1–4 because, although every rule tested was clearly framed as a deontic conditional, most failed to elicit good violation detection.

This is most strikingly demonstrated by the results of experiment 4, where the same social contract, with the same interpretation, was used in every condition. Despite holding the rule and its interpretation constant, we predicted and found systematic decreases in violation detection. This was accomplished by subtracting cues that the search for violations might reveal people with a disposition to cheat. Each cue removed dropped performance by ~20 percentage points, from a high of 64% (three cues) to 46% (two cues) to 26% (one cue).

Economic and Utility Consequences Ruled Out

Economics, utility theory, behaviorism, and common sense all lead to the expectation that a lifetime of not getting what you are entitled to would build skill at detecting violations of social contracts. Yet our subjects were not good at detecting these violations unless doing so might reveal a cheater—someone who had intentionally taken the benefit without meeting the requirement.

Some reasoning researchers take a similar tack. To explain why social contracts and precautionary rules—but not other deontic conditionals—elicit good violation detection, they propose that the deontic rule must involve utilities, and that a rule violation must have consequences for someone’s utility [e.g., Manktelow and Over (1991); Kirby (1994), Oaksford and Chater (1994) on optimal data selection and decision theory; Sperber et al. (1995) on relevance theory]. However, the results of experiments 3

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

and 4 cannot be explained by these theories either. The school problem was a social contract and, whether it is violated by accident or intent, in all cases violations will produce an event with consequences for other people’s utility: someone’s child will get access to a benefit they are not entitled to, and the school board (and taxpayers) will experience a loss—they will incur the expense of providing a benefit to families that did not pay for it (on loss, see Fiddick and Rutherford (2006); SI Text, note 3].

The most dramatic demonstration that “consequences for utility” is an inadequate explanation comes from comparing the four benefit-present conditions of experiment 4 (BIA, BI, BA, B; Fig. 15.2). A rule violation has obvious consequences for utility in all of these cases: A volunteer will benefit if her child is assigned to a good school that she did not pay for—a point which is brought to the subject’s attention (SI Text, note 2). Yet performance decreased as a function of intention and ability, from 64% in the BIA condition, to 41% and 46% in the BA (intention removed) and BI (ability removed) conditions, to 26% in the B condition (intention and ability removed). Indeed, the relevance [sensu Sperber et al. (1995)] of discovering violations is highest in the BI condition, because this would reveal that the anti-cheating measures taken are ineffective, that people are intentionally breaking the rule despite these measures, and that they are getting an unearned benefit by doing so. Yet performance in this condition was lower than for the BIA condition, and similar to performance in the BA condition, where there was no intention to cheat.

Lastly, the deontic + utility theories cannot explain the results by claiming—post hoc—that violation detection procedures are simply not activated by the prospect of accidents and other innocent mistakes. If this were true, then violation detection should suffer when people are asked to look for accidental violations of precautionary rules; like social contracts, these are deontic conditionals involving utilities. Yet the accident-intention manipulation has no effect whatsoever on precautionary rules: people easily detect accidental violations of them (Fiddick, 2004). This is what one would expect if they were being processed by the precautionary system—an adaptive specialization with a different evolved function.

The Remarkable Functional Specificity of Cheater Detection Algorithms

Progress is made not only by ruling out rival theories but by mapping additional design features in the architecture of social contract algorithms. These experiments clarify a number of design features of the social contract inferential specialization. Based on the distinctive pattern in which violation detection is up-regulated and down-regulated, we now know that at least three cues independently contribute to cheater detection. First,

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

intentional violations activate cheater detection, but innocent mistakes do not. Second, violation detection is up-regulated when potential violators would get the benefit regulated by the rule, and down-regulated when they would not. Third, cheater detection is down-regulated when the situation makes cheating difficult—when violations are unlikely, the search for them is unlikely to reveal those with a disposition to cheat. This provides three converging lines of evidence that the mechanism implicated is not designed to look for general rule violators, or deontic rule violators, or violators of social contracts, or even cases in which someone has been cheated; it does not deign to look for violators of social exchange rules in cases of mistake—not even in cases when someone has accidentally benefited by violating a social contract. Instead, this Inspector Javert-like system is monomaniacally focused on looking for social contract rule violations when this is likely to lead to detecting cheaters—defined as agents who obtain a rationed benefit while intentionally not meeting the requirement.

Consider, however, that this system has the computational power to detect social contract violations—it must, to detect cheaters. Yet it is regulated so that violation detection is deployed only in the service of cheater detection. It is difficult to think of a more powerful signal of the system’s functional specificity than that.

Specializations, Modularity, and Intelligence

Finally, our results prompt a rethinking of the relationship between functional specificity and modular accounts of intelligence. The term module was originally borrowed from engineering, to refer to a device specialized to perform a specific function. This meaning dovetails nicely with the concept of an adaptive specialization. Unfortunately, this simple and useful definition became encrusted with additional concepts after the publication of Fodor’s book, the Modularity of Mind, in which he argued that “information encapsulation” is an important, if not criterial, property of mental modules. This led many cognitive scientists to construe modules as inherently noninteractive, inflexible, reflex-like, and narrow, partitioning information into compartments or pipelines where it is incapable of interacting with other information (Fodor, 1983).

Our results show that the cheater detection system is highly specialized to perform a specific function, which fits the original definition of a module. There is also a very weak sense in which it is informationally encapsulated: to perform its function, it requires representations of interactions among agents that fit the benefit-requirement template of a social contract. But it is nothing like an information pipeline.

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

In contrast to the Fodorian view, our results show that in monitoring for cheaters, multiple inferential processes are simultaneously brought to bear. It requires a system that infers agent-specific utilities, which itself recruits a number of more specialized systems. To assess the benefits taken and requirements met in social exchanges, this system had to compute the interests of the parties involved—inferring, for example, that processing one’s own children’s documents implies a potential to benefit through a kin relationship, though this is never explicitly stated. That the cheater detection system responds more strongly to intentional violations than to innocent mistakes implies that it monitors the intentions of the parties involved, suggesting recruitment of specialized inferential mechanisms known as “mindreading” or “theory of mind” (Baron-Cohen, 1995). That it monitors how the ability of subjects to cheat might be constrained by causal properties of the situation, such as access to relevant information, implicates additional processes of causal reasoning. And all of these inferences were applied not to a real situation, but to an imagined one, implying a system that allows suppositional reasoning to occur in a way that is decoupled from semantic memory (Leslie, 1987; Cosmides and Tooby, 2001).

The fact that these processes interact in determining subjects’ choices in our tasks suggests that the cheater detection mechanism, despite being a specialized, modular process, does not operate in isolation from other specialized, modular processes such as a kinship psychology, theory of mind, and causal reasoning (Leslie, 1987; Baron-Cohen, 1995; Lieberman et al., 2007). Instead, multiple mechanisms interact synergistically. From a functionalist point of view this should not be surprising, given that cognitive scientists have long held that the adaptive benefit of carving up complex problems into smaller parts is to leverage the synergistic gains afforded by the interaction of specialized processes, much like in an economy (Simon, 1962; Minksy, 1995; Barrett, 2005). However, it clearly falsifies a common but mistaken view of modularity as noninteractivity, a view that has led to widespread but mistaken resistance to modular, adaptationist views of cognition. Contrary to that view, emergent synergies of interacting parts are the hallmark of evolved specialized design. This means that it is likely that no single ability alone, such as cooperation, or theory of mind, or causal reasoning, is likely to explain the unique aspects of human intelligence. Instead, a complete account of human intelligence is likely to require explaining both how multiple cognitive abilities interact, and the novel forms of flexibility that those interactions afford (Barrett et al., 2007).

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×

CONCLUSIONS

An evolutionary approach to human intelligence leads to the radically different—and highly counterintuitive—view that our cognitive architecture includes evolved reasoning programs that were specialized by selection for distinct adaptive problems, such as social exchange and evading hazards. Although such a view strikes many as implausible in the extreme—why would anything in the mind be so strangely specialized?—the careful analysis of adaptive problems allows the derivation of rich sets of testable and unique predictions about our cognitive architecture. When these predictions are empirically tested—as here—the results typically support the view that the human cognitive architecture contains specializations for adaptive problems our ancestors faced. In this case, we can show that the cheater detection system functions with pinpoint accuracy, remaining inactive not only on rules outside the domain of social exchange but also on social exchanges that show little promise of revealing a cheater. In the contest of intuition versus evidence, it will be interesting to see which will prove the more persuasive. Human intelligence, like the sediments of east Africa, may preserve powerful signals from the evolutionary past. And, maybe, the Earth really does orbit the sun.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

The authors thank Roger N. Shepard, the National Institutes of Health Directors’ Pioneer Award to L.C., the National Science Foundation Young Investigator Award to J.T., the James S. McDonnell Foundation, and a UCSB Academic Senate grant.

Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 293
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 294
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 295
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 296
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 297
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 298
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 299
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 300
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 301
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 302
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 303
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 304
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 305
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 306
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 307
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 308
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 309
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 310
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 311
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 312
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 313
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 314
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 315
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 316
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 317
Suggested Citation:"15 Adaptive Specializations, Social Exchange, and the Evolution of Human Intelligence--Leda Cosmides, H. Clark Barrett, and John Tooby ." National Academy of Sciences. 2010. In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/12931.
×
Page 318
Next: 16 The Difference of Being Human: Morality--Francisco J. Ayala »
In the Light of Evolution: Volume IV: The Human Condition Get This Book
×
Buy Hardback | $75.00 Buy Ebook | $59.99
MyNAP members save 10% online.
Login or Register to save!
Download Free PDF

The Human Condition is a collection of papers by leading evolutionary biologists and philosophers of science that reflect on the Darwinian Revolution as it relates to the human condition at levels ranging from the molecular to the theological. The book focuses on understanding the evolutionary origin of humans and their biological and cultural traits. The Human Condition is organized into three parts: Human Phylogenetic History and the Paleontological Record; Structure and Function of the Human Genome; and Cultural Evolution and the Uniqueness of Being Human.

This fourth volume from the In the Light of Evolution (ILE) series, based on a series of Arthur M. Sackler colloquia, was designed to promote the evolutionary sciences. Each volume explores evolutionary perspectives on a particular biological topic that is scientifically intriguing but also has special relevance to contemporary societal issues or challenges. Individually and collectively, the ILE series interprets phenomena in various areas of biology through the lens of evolution, addresses some of the most intellectually engaging as well as pragmatically important societal issues of our times, and fosters a greater appreciation of evolutionary biology as a consolidating foundation for the life sciences.

  1. ×

    Welcome to OpenBook!

    You're looking at OpenBook, NAP.edu's online reading room since 1999. Based on feedback from you, our users, we've made some improvements that make it easier than ever to read thousands of publications on our website.

    Do you want to take a quick tour of the OpenBook's features?

    No Thanks Take a Tour »
  2. ×

    Show this book's table of contents, where you can jump to any chapter by name.

    « Back Next »
  3. ×

    ...or use these buttons to go back to the previous chapter or skip to the next one.

    « Back Next »
  4. ×

    Jump up to the previous page or down to the next one. Also, you can type in a page number and press Enter to go directly to that page in the book.

    « Back Next »
  5. ×

    Switch between the Original Pages, where you can read the report as it appeared in print, and Text Pages for the web version, where you can highlight and search the text.

    « Back Next »
  6. ×

    To search the entire text of this book, type in your search term here and press Enter.

    « Back Next »
  7. ×

    Share a link to this book page on your preferred social network or via email.

    « Back Next »
  8. ×

    View our suggested citation for this chapter.

    « Back Next »
  9. ×

    Ready to take your reading offline? Click here to buy this book in print or download it as a free PDF, if available.

    « Back Next »
Stay Connected!